Intended recipient

Clive D.W. Feather clive at davros.org
Wed Sep 14 12:23:21 BST 2011


Peter Fairbrother said:
> The first kind, who the intended recipient is, is almost entirely clear. 
> Intention exists only in the human mind, and in this case the only mind 
> involved is that of the sender. It is what is in his mind which counts, 
> and the intended recipient of a communication is the recipient he has in 
> mind when he sends the communication.
> 
> Someone reading the address of a misaddressed communication might 
> believe that the intended recipient was someone other than the recipient 
> the sender intended, but he would be mistaken - the actual intended 
> recipient is always the person the sender intends to receive the message.

While they might be mistaken, is that mistakeness sufficient to negate mens
rea? I suspect this would be a question of fact for the jury rather than a
question of law.

> The second kind of intent, which is required for a person's actions to 
> be a crime, is less clear. ss.1(1) says "It shall be an offence for a 
> person intentionally and without lawful authority to intercept..."
> 
> But intention to do what? Intention to intercept? Intention to intercept 
> without lawful authority?

The former. If it meant the latter it would say "intentionally to intercept
without lawful authority". It's clear, at least to me, that this is parsed
as:
    a person ((intentionally to intercept ...) and (without lawful
    authority to intercept ...))

> Does a genuine but mistaken 
> belief that a person's actions have lawful authority, while knowing 
> those actions to be interception, prevent those actions from being an 
> offence? I am not clear on that point.

Surely that's exactly the point on which Cliff Stanford got convicted? He
believed he had lawful authority, and he even had a QC's opinion to back
him up.

> Further, interception was defined in section 2, and later the definition 
> may be refined by Judges, but seldom will a person decide his actions on 
> exactly that definition.

See above.

> If a person genuinely believes his actions are 
> not interception then they are not an offence under ss.1(1), as it is 
> not his intention to intercept.

However, a person is deemed to know the law. So the question is not what
he thinks that "interception" means, but what it *actually* means.

So if he is misinterpreting s.2, he's still committing an offence. If he's
misinterpreting the *facts* as to whether his actions are (say) "modifying"
(e.g. he didn't realize that the wire he attached the crocodile clips to
was part of a public network) *then* he has a defence.

> It is even unclear whether a person's intent is relevant. It is quite 
> possible to interpret "as to" to have strictly the meaning that the 
> outcome of the potential interceptor's actions is or would have been 
> that content was made available, irrespective of what was in the 
> potential interceptor's mind.

I don't think a court would accept this was a strict liability offence,
because there's none of the wording that would imply that.

-- 
Clive D.W. Feather          | If you lie to the compiler,
Email: clive at davros.org     | it will get its revenge.
Web: http://www.davros.org  |   - Henry Spencer
Mobile: +44 7973 377646



More information about the ukcrypto mailing list